Although
evolution as it is presently understood involves a very long process of natural
selection (among other arbitrary processes) without an overarching goal or
forward progression toward a pre-defined or predictable result, this is not
always appreciated. Some tend to believe, or
at least act as if they believe, that evolution has accomplished its goal
and reached its pinnacle, the end result being a species we’ve self-classified
as homo sapien. Perhaps that is to be expected given that we are the only
species capable of writing On The Origin Of Species and similar books that aim to explain the
evolution of ourselves to ourselves. This hubristic tendency to think that
evolution has done its work and the mantle is now passed to our capable hands
(with opposable thumbs!) to mold reality as we wish engenders another false
narrative, namely that we can figure everything out.
Because we comprehend
many things, there is a tendency to think that we can eventually comprehend all
things. This, however, is most likely not
the case. It is more probable that there
are facts beyond the grasp of human beings, facts which can never be
represented or comprehended by us, no matter how much we believe the opposite.
Forty years
ago the philosopher Thomas Nagel wrote an essay titled “What Is It Like To Be A
Bat?”. The thrust of the article concerns questions of consciousness and
specifically the mind-body problem of consciousness, but at the periphery of the
discussion Nagel touches briefly on another topic, which he describes as “the relation
between facts on the one hand and conceptual schemes or systems of
representation on the other.” It is this
line of thought, coupled with the notion of subjectivity, which prompted him to
invoke a “belief in the existence of facts beyond the reach of human concepts.”
Nagel writes,
“Indeed, it would be foolish to doubt this, given (human) finiteness. There are
facts which could not ever be
comprehended by human beings, even if the species lasted for ever – simply
because our structure does not permit us to operate with concepts of the requisite
type.” Nagel uses the example of a bat
and what it is like to experience reality as this strange, nocturnal mammal as
a way of highlighting the difficulties in a reductionist theory of conscious
subjective experience. This example is also useful when considering our
inaccessibility of certain facts.
Nagel chooses
bats because they are mammals like us, a higher order vertebrate that doubtless
has experience. Bats, although sharing our mammalian heritage, are nevertheless
a species that Nagel describes as a “fundamentally alien form of life” since
they “present a range of activity and a sensory apparatus so different from
ours that the problem is exceptionally vivid.” Most bats perceive the external world by
using echolocation, a form of sonar. Bats emit high-frequency sounds that
reflect off objects within range. Their
brains then correlate these outgoing and incoming impulses to gather
information that enable them to determine size, distance, movement and other
factors which effectively correspond with our sense of vision.
Even though we
can understand and describe the principle of echolocation and recognize that it
is a form of “bat vision”, our ability to conceive what such an experience
would be like is “restricted to the
resources of our own minds, and those resources are inadequate to the
task.” It is, according to Nagel, “not
similar in its operation to any sense that we possess, and there is no reason
to suppose that it is subjectively like anything we can experience or imagine.”
It will not help my case to think of
myself hanging upside-down from a cave by my feet, or growing webbed wings and
eating insects in the night sky by locating them with shrill sounds. These images tell me only what it is like for me to behave like a bat. What
we want to know is what it is like for
a bat to be a bat.
The same
difficulty arises when we consider what it would be like for an alien species
(a race of intelligent Martians, let’s say) to form a conception of what it is
like to be us. As Nagel suggests, “the structure of their
own minds might make it impossible for them to succeed, but we know they would
be wrong to conclude that there is not anything precise that it is like to be
us: that only certain general types of mental state could be ascribed to us
(perhaps perception and appetite would be concepts common to us both; perhaps
not). We know they would be wrong to draw such a skeptical conclusion because
we know what it is like to be us.”
Similarly, it might prove as improbable for us to conceptualize or
comprehend the subjective experiences of alien beings vastly more intelligent
than ourselves, since it could be the case that dissimilar structures of our
respective mental processes would create an insurmountable barrier.
Nagel argues
that “the fact that we cannot expect ever to accommodate in our language a
detailed description of Martian or bat phenomenology should not lead us to
dismiss as meaningless the claim that bats and Martians have experiences fully
comparable in richness of detail to our own.”
The case that the subjective experiences of bats and Martians are facts from
which humans are excluded from understanding does not invalidate the
proposition that they nevertheless constitute a set of facts. An extension of this rationale is the idea
that since it is impossible for humans to represent or comprehend facts that
our limited structure (and the limits of our technological inventions) prevent,
the possibility exists that facts which are clearly evident to other creatures remain
unknown to us. “After all, the nature of
beings with access to humanly inaccessible facts is presumably itself a humanly
inaccessible fact”, Nagel suggests. Only
those facts to which we have access are meaningful to us. This limited set does not constitute the
whole. It is merely the set to which we
can gain access.
In summary,
Nagel offers this thought, “It would be fine if someone were to develop
concepts and a theory that enabled us to think about those things; but such an understanding
may be permanently denied to us by the limits of our nature. And to deny the reality
or logical significance of what we can never describe or understand is the
crudest form of cognitive dissonance.”
No comments:
Post a Comment